This article argues that in the absence of
normative criteria that can identify a set of universal human rights,
the "right to have constitutional rights" can take on the onus of being
that universal human right. In the case of honour killings, the right to
have and, more importantly, access legitimate fundamental and legal
rights is under severe doubt. A universal standard framework - such as a
reading of "right to have rights" would have it - justifies the very
purpose of human rights itself. The origin of human rights, thus, shifts
from the matter of "being human" to a matter of social, political and
legal constructivism.
Sneha Annavarapu (
a.sneha91@gmail.com)
is doing her integrated MA in the Department of Development Studies and
Social Sciences, Indian Institute of Technology, Chennai.
There are several definitions of “honour killings” abound. Welchman
and Hossain make a valid observation that most definitions of “honour
crimes” or honour killings arise by the way of illustration (2005: 7).
According to the Human Rights Watch, the mere perception that “a woman
has behaved in a way that ‘dishonours’” her family is sufficient to
trigger an attack on her life (Kirti et al 2011: 344). Following
Nasrullah, Haqqi, and Cummings,
1 for the purposes of this
article, we will be defining honour killings as those murders that occur
when a person (or persons) transgresses norms imposed by her/his
community in the name of preserving honour as culturally prescribed.
These norms may be with regard to sexual autonomy, marriage, religious
conscience, caste, property, etc, all of which construct honour in ways
that this article will explore.
In 2000, the United Nations (UN) estimated that there are around
5,000 honour killings every year worldwide (Chesler 2010: 3). In India,
statistics from 2010 indicate roughly 900 reported honour killings in
Haryana, Punjab and Uttar Pradesh, while additional 100-300 honour
killings took place in the rest of the country (Chesler and Bloom 2012:
45). Despite international conventions like the Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW), honour
killings in countries such as Jordan, Pakistan, India, etc, are rampant
and the victims are not just women – although they are predominantly
women – but also men who exercise certain personal freedoms and “sexual
deviants” such as transgenders.
2 The prevalence of “crimes of
honour” in several nations (GoI 2012: 2-3) highlights the relevance of
using a framework of international law to address this macrosocial
malaise. Is there a feasible mechanism through which we can address this
invidious crime across all nations?
The language of human rights – best represented by the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) – is pervasive in ethics, law,
political theory, sociology, anthropology and other domains. The
influence of human rights is tangible, especially in the fields of
international relations and law. While a detailed engagement with all
the dimensions of the human rights is outside the purview of the
purposes of this article, I will explore the adjudication of khap
panchayats in matters relating to marriage. It looks at the
International Bill of Human Rights which deals with the aspects of the
“right to marry” (to borrow Martha Nussbaum’s (2010) phraseology) and
will provide a plausible solution to the debate surrounding universalism
and cultural particularism in human rights discourses.
I base my arguments on the premise that the “aspirational” idea
behind the documentation of universal human rights is put under severe
duress owing to the recurrent and recalcitrant presence of honour
killings in various countries and that the idea of “individualism” and
“choice” is challenged by the prevalence of informal social systems
which rely on ideas of “culture” – however contentious that term may be.
The very fact that honour crimes stand at the confluence of “competing
spheres of legal subjection simultaneously – customary laws, family law,
criminal law and international law – makes this a very challenging case
to study” (Baxi et al 2006: 1240).
An analysis of honour killings in India would be incomplete without
an understanding of the origins of social systems that typify and
actively promote this social phenomenon. Currently, honour killings in
India are perpetrated most notably by the khap panchayats in states like
Haryana, Uttar Pradesh, Punjab, parts of Bihar, and Rajasthan and katta
panchayats in parts of Tamil Nadu.
3 The concept of khaps is
said to date back to 2500 BC and is essentially an archaic form of
social administration. A khap can be defined as a unit comprising 84
villages belonging to the same
gotra.
4 A khap
panchayat is a council of five elders of the village who look after the
administration of the village. With the introduction of the panchayati
raj system via the 73rd and 74th Amendment Acts, official village
panchayats have been established all over the country. Despite their
legal and official status, village panchayats in some parts of the
country are heavily dominated and coerced by these informal social
systems like the khap panchayats (Kachhwaha 2011: 298).
Khap panchayats are said to adjudicate on matters related to social
transgressions, marriage, property rights, inheritance, and caste issues
(ibid: 298-99). The development of non-state parallel systems of
adjudication has, especially after Independence, resulted in the
constructions of gender and sexuality, tradition and honour.
5 In this article, we will explore the adjudication of khap panchayats in matters relating to marriage.
Marriage as a Right
In India, the right to marry is a component of “right to life” as
enshrined by Article 21 of the Constitution of India. It is not simply
the “right to marry”, but it is the right to marry out of choice.
However, as Perveez Mody has rightly noted, in India, the idea of
“choice” is not individual as much as it is filial or social (2002:
226). Legally speaking, however, in the iconic case
Lata Singh vs State of Uttar Pradesh
(2006, SC 2522), the Supreme Court observed that, “This is a free and
democratic country, and once a person becomes a major he or she can
marry whosoever he/she likes”.
6
According to the present legal system in India, citizens have a
choice between respective religion-based and community-specific marriage
laws and general and common laws of civil marriages. While the former
unions are supervised by “personal laws”, the latter unions are codified
by the Special Marriage Act, 1954
7 and the Foreign Marriage Act, 1969. The Indian legal system, technically, allows for marriages that are
sagotra8
since it does not recognise gotra as being the defining unit of a
family. While the Indian Penal Code (IPC), 1980 is yet to explicitly
criminalise “incest”,
9 village courts such as khap panchayats
have taken it upon themselves to punish individuals engaging in sagotra
marriages since, they argue, it would amount to incest (GoI 2012: 4).
Khap panchayats denounce marriages that are inter-caste and violently
react to marriages that are intra-gotra. Both of these unions are
legally recognised by the Constitution of India and are not criminalised
by the IPC, 1860. In fact, the Hindu Marriage Disabilities Removal
Act, 1946 was passed and enacted in order to reinforce this notion of
choice and free will in choosing one’s partner (ibid: 4-5). The Supreme
Court reacted strongly against village courts in
Arumugam Servai vs State of Tamil Nadu (reported in 2011) 6 SCC 405 (ibid: 5).
The UDHR
10 can be read to assert the notion of free will when it comes to marriage in Article 16.
11
Apart from the explicit recognition of marrying out of choice in the
UDHR, there are several other guarantees that are complicit in the
assertion of free will and choice when it comes to matrimony. For
instance, the preamble of the UDHR reaffirms the “faith in fundamental
human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person and in the
equal rights of men and women”, while also ensuring to uphold the
“freedom from fear and want”. Article 3 espouses that everyone has the
right to life, liberty and security while Article 5 prohibits torture
and inhuman treatment and/or punishment. Article 8 guarantees effective
remedial procedures in national judiciary systems for acts that violate
the fundamental rights guaranteed by the national constitution. Article
12 prohibits arbitrary interference with privacy, family, home or
correspondence including attacks on honour and reputation. The honour
killings occurring everywhere in the world violate every single one
of these articles. The UDHR also espouses the right to the protection of law against such attacks by Article 30
12 which acts as an umbrella right that acts as a barrier against any infringement of the rights enumerated in the UDHR.
The very notion that universal human rights are applicable to all
human beings irrespective of any other consideration is important here.
While the idea of “marriage” is a universal one, the terms and
conditions of its execution and substance are culturally specific. A
liberal view of marriage would consider it to be a matter of individual
choice and freedom, whereas some communities – as in this case –
consider it to be tied to ideas of lineage, honour and religion. It is
obvious that the human right to life is violated by honour killings, but
is there something more to this violence? Is there a metaphysical
dimension to this idea of physical violence? What is the role of
tradition and how does it justify killing people for the sake of honour?
These are some of the aspects we shall cover in the next section.
Tradition, Marriage and Honour
As Martha Nussbaum (2010: 668) states:
For many, if not most people, marriage is not a trivial
matter. It is a key to the pursuit of happiness, something people aspire
to – and keep aspiring to, again and again, even when their experience
has been far from happy.
There are two elements in this statement that have strong
implications when they come to culturally specific understandings of
“marriage”. First, the fact that marriage is not a trivial matter is
reflected in the fact that “crimes of honour” and honour killings often
occur due to the fact that certain individuals have flouted the
society’s normative stance regarding matrimony (Baxi 2006; Kachhwaha
2011; Viswanath and Palakonda 2011; GoI 2012).
Second, unlike the liberal notion of “pursuit of happiness”, in
countries like India, marriages occur for a variety of reasons ranging
from basic notions of “carrying forward the bloodline” to pecuniary
motives like property acquisition to the more contemporary notions of
love and exercise of choice.
13 In rural India, the notion of
“proper” marriages is intertwined with adhering to certain norms in
society which when disregarded cause disrepute to the family and kin of
the “accused”. As is indicated by all the papers referred to in this
article, one of the most prominent reasons to execute an honour killing
is when persons do not adhere to the traditional norms of society and
marry out of choice vis-à-vis out of consent by the elders in the
village. This is said to bring “dishonour” upon the family of the person
engaging in such activity. Punishments can be fines (nominal or
substantial), ritual expiation, public humiliation (ranging from
blackening of face to dipping victim’s nose in human urine), forcing
her/him to host a feast for the village, beating up, and/or banishment
from the village (Yadav 2009: 17). Of course, honour killings
automatically imply the harshest punishment of all – murder.
In an interesting analysis of the conception of honour, Johanna Bond
(2012) has argued that there are definite intersections between the
constructions of honour and the construction of property in societies.
She also uses a lens of property in order to map gender-based violence
in patriarchal societies. In the case of khap panchayats, scholars
(Mhatre 2010; Ahlawat 2012) have already pointed to the strong linkages
between land, property and norms regarding marriage as formulated by
khap panchayats. Does honour have a specific role to play in the denial
of free choice? Annie George
14 points out that:
Honour is thought to reside primarily, but not exclusively, in the
bodies of women and is maintained through female chastity, virtue, and
subdued body language, dress, and demeanor. Individual honour is usually
subsumed to family and religious or caste community honour, which,
typically, is maintained through restrictions on women’s movements,
opportunities, and life choices.
The observation about the restriction of “choice” clearly collides
with liberal ideas of choice, individual agency and personal freedoms.
As S K Araji (2000) has noted, the idea of honour is external –
dependent on the norms imposed by an external agent – and requires the
sanction of a social system. This can be contrasted with a liberal view
of honour as being internally sourced and lying with the individual.
Furthermore, the single-minded focus on women indicates a skewed notion
of equitable and equal access to rights.
15 Baxi et al (2006)
discuss the notion of the Rule of Law in relation to the complexities
inherent in a postcolonial terrain such as India where the tension
between the forces of “tradition” and “modernity” is evident in informal
systems such as khap panchayats. In the next section, we will juxtapose
the legal aspects of marriage in formal Indian law and international
law and trace the tensions between the written word and the ground
reality.
A Tentative Solution
The friction between universalism and cultural relativism is manifest
in the case of honour killings and honour crimes by khap panchayats. As
argued earlier in this article, it is not just the act of the murder of
“erring” individuals but it is the process behind the construction of
honour which is the bone of contention here. The liberal notion of
“individual agency” is in direct contrast with the notion of collective
social agency and stringent norms. Arguing that human rights are indeed
natural rights that are not given by any particular authority, but are
inherent in the fact that one is born a human being, Jack Donnelly
(1984, 2007) points to the universality of certain basic human rights as
being both a positive and a normative issue. It is not just that there
are certain inalienable universal rights but that it is a matter of
advantage and gain that this is the case. Elizabeth Zechenter in a
brilliant analysis of “cultural relativism” (1997) also supports this
claim of Donnelly’s that relativism and cultural particularism can be
abused by states in order to engage in unethical practices against
people.
In the case of honour killings by khap panchayats, one can see that
if adherence to a particular cultural practice is imposed in the name of
“tradition”, the attack is not just on the individuals but on the
institution of individual choice based on a conscious agency protected
by the tenets of a Rule of Law which is assumed to be based on universal
notions of justice and fairness. Thus, it is not just the marriage that
is questioned but the exercise of free will in deciding whom to marry.
It is obvious that universal notions of justice would deem the denial of
such an exercise invalid, and even, horrifying. However, if we take the
standpoint of relativism, it becomes contingent on the cultural ethos
and values of that particular community. This is in violation of human
rights as understood as something not dependent on an external source or
not being a privilege – an argument that Donnelly (1982) has made,
while trying to justify the origin of contemporary human rights as being
an exclusively western one. The right to have rights is itself violated
in the case of denial of fundamental rights which are
not
“given
” by the State
but are
ensured
by it. This subtle distinction has immense ramifications.
In this debate on universalism and cultural relativism of human
rights, I would like to propose a mediating stance whereby the validity
of both these ends remains intact much like the aspiration of “quality
control” that Philip Alston (1984) had called for. Borrowing from
Terence Turner’s proposal of a “universal right to difference” (Turner
1997), I borrow the methodological relativism to an entirely
oppositional conclusion. However, while this can be theoretically
defended, it is harder to implement owing to political disinclinations.
My basic argument is that since in the international discourse on human
rights there seems to be a disagreement of what constitutes “human”
rights owing to accusations of western dominance,
16 we can use Hannah Arendt’s conception of “right to have rights” although not in terms of citizenship as was intended by her
17
but in terms of human dignity and the constant need to engage in a
dialectic between fundamental rights and human rights. The fact that
certain rights are codified in the Constitution does not automatically
translate into their proper protection – there is the need for a
universal human right to guarantees of culturally relative fundamental
rights as enshrined in the constitution of each state, if we take the
state to be the political community that we are concerned with.
Therefore, the argument of cultural relativism in terms of honour
killings would be deemed invalid by the universal human right to have
constitutional rights protected. The constitutional rights of a country
are privileged at the behest of the access to those rights becoming a
human right.
Pointing to the fact that the current legal system in India is a
colonial legacy, Baxi et al (2006) analyse the impact of a modern, alien
Rule of Law to the traditional structures of polity (such as khap
panchayats) in India. They observe that the rise in “honour killings” is
a reaction against the construction of a modern notion of justice and
law in which the attempt is to inscribe tradition in clear boundaries
that can be attributed to the authenticity of an “Indian culture”. In a
report by the Law Commission of India, there was a call to criminalise
honour killings by making it a penal offence under the IPC, 1860 and/or
making a congregation of elder members in the village itself illegal
(GoI 2012). While I admit to the effectiveness of these solutions,
unless the international community is involved using the crutch of a
universal human right which is not mired in controversies surrounding
its content, the seriousness of honour killings will be under severe
doubt which will make it harder to prevent future incidents in this
regard.
It becomes hard to justify the universality of a right that is
particular in terms of substance. I argue that form can be universal.
For instance, if the human right is specific on how it defines “free
choice”, the relativists can raise questions pertaining to the origin of
this idea of free choice since the substance of the right is
articulated and that substance is cultural. However, it is harder to
find issues with the form of a right such as the right to have rights
since it is an a priori right that is not defining the tenets of “being
human” but is articulating the right to have rights that are culturally
specific or “aspecific”.
In terms of implementation, this kind of an “umbrella right” is hard
to execute owing to the political machinery in the country. Not only is
there a problem with whether the constitutional rights are just and
fair, but the question of how does having an umbrella right to have
rights make any difference to the institutional execution required for
any effect to be palpable comes up. While I admit to the weaknesses in
terms of execution, there is a facility in terms of at least
theoretically coming to a “relatively universal” solution to the problem
of conflicting perspectives on the universality of human rights.
Notes
1 As cited in Dorjee et al (2013: 3).
2 The magnitude of honour killings is, thus, not restricted to men
and/or women, but empirical evidence shows that the victims are mostly
women. The construction of “gender” and the notions of masculinity,
femininity and queer in the case of honour killings is an interesting
route to take in order to deconstruct this violent phenomenon. However,
for the purposes of this article, I shall be sticking to “given”
categories of male/female.
3 See GoI (2012).
4 The closest English translation is the word “clan”. There is a belief that at the beginning of existence, there were seven
rishis/saints who generated seven clans and thus, by extension, all those born into a particular clan are brothers and sisters.
5 Vishwanath and Palakonda (2011). While these three are inextricably
linked in a web of patriarchy, a discussion using a feminist lens is
out of the scope of this paper.
6 See GoI (2008), 17-19. Of course, there are “reasonable
restrictions” to this fundamental right, such as the concept of
“prohibiting degrees in marriage” which explicitly denounces the
validity of a marriage between relatives as codified by family law.
7 The first law of civil marriages in India was governed by the
Special Marriage Act, 1872 enacted during the British Rule in India. For
details regarding that and other legal specifications, please refer to a
report by Law Commission of India (GoI 2008).
8 Within the same gotra or clan, as defined in Note 4.
9 Karthikeya, “We Need Special Laws to Deal with Incest”,
The Times of India, 23 May 2009. Link:
http://articles.timesofindia.indiatimes.com/ 2009-03-23/mumbai/28020095_1_incest-laws-crime, accessed on 13 April 2013.
10 For the full text, please visit:
http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/index.shtml
11 Article 16 states that:
(1) Men and women of full age, without any limitation due to race,
nationality or religion, have the right to marry and to found a family.
They are entitled to equal rights as to marriage, during marriage and at
its dissolution.
(2) Marriage shall be entered into only with the free and full consent of the intending spouses.
(3) The family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to protection by society and the state.
12 Article 30 states that “Nothing in this Declaration may be
interpreted as implying for any State, group or person any right to
engage in any activity or to perform any act aimed at the destruction of
any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein.”.
13 For more depth in the sociological analyses of the family
structure in India, please refer to Dyson and Moore (1983) and Madsen
(1991).
14 As cited in Bond (2012: 12).
15 For a detailed discussion on patriarchal ideology and the notion
of honour in village courts, please read Vishwanath and Palakonda
(2011).
16 Further accusations of how this thrives on a conflation of modernisation with westernisation.
17 Helis (2008) has used such a reading of Arendt too.
References
Ahlawat, Neerja (2012): “The Political Economy of Haryana’s Khaps”,
Economic & Political Weekly, Vol XLVII, Nos 47-48, pp 15-17.
Alston, Philip (1984): “Conjuring Up New Human Rights: A Proposal for Quality Con
trol”, The American Journal of International Law, Vol 78, No 3: 607-21.
Araji, S K (2000): “Crimes of Honor and Shame: Violence against Women in Non-Western and Western Societies”,
The Red Feather Journal of Postmodern Criminology, an international journal,
http://critcrim.org/redfeather/journal-pomocrim/vol-8-shaming/araji.html, accessed on 12 April 2013.
Baxi, Pratiksha (2006): “Habeas Corpus in the Realm of Lo
ve: Litigating Marriages of Choice in India”,
The Australian Feminist Law Journal, Vol 25, 59-78.
Baxi, Pratiksha, Shirin M Rai and Shaheen Sardar Ali (2006): “Legacies of Common Law: ‘Crimes of Honour’’ in India and Pakistan
”, Third World Quarterly, 27: 7, 1239-53.
Bond, Johanna (2012): “Honor as Property”,
Columbia Journall on Gender and Law, http://ssrn.com/abstract= 2055326, accessed on 3 March 2013.
Chesler, Phyllis (2010): “Worldwide Trends in Honor Killings
”, Middle East Quarterly, Spring, 3-11.
Chesler, Phyllis and Nathan Bloom (2012): “Hindu vs Muslim Honor Killings”,
Middle East Quarterly, Summer 2012: 43-52.
Donnelly, Jack (1982): “Human Rights and Human Dignity: An Analytic Critique of Non Western Conceptions of Human Rights”,
The American Political Science Review, Vol 76, No 2: 303-16.
– (1984): “Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights”,
Human Rights Quarterly, Vol 6, No 4: 400-19.
– (2007): “The Relative Universality of Human Rights”,
Human Rights Quarterly, Vol 29, No 2: 281-306.
Dorjee, Tenzin, Noorie Baig and Stella Ting-Toomey (2013): “A Social
Ecological Perspective on Understanding ‘Honor Killing’: An
Intercultural Moral Dilemma”,
Journal of Intercultural Communication Research, Vol 42, No 1: 1-21.
Dyson, Tim and Dick Moore (1983): “On Kinship Structure, Female Autonomy, and Demographic Behaviour in India”,
Population and Development Review, Vol 9, No 1: 35-60.
GoI (2008):
Laws of Civil Marriages in India – A Proposal to Resolve Certain Conflicts (Report No 212) (New Delhi: Law Commissi
on of India, Government of India).
– (2012):
Prevention of Interference with the Freedom of
Matrimonial Alliances (in the Name of Honour and Tradition): A Suggested
Legal Framework (New Delhi: Law Commission of India, Government of India).
Helis, John (2008): “Hannah Arendt and Human Dignity: Theoretical Foundations and Constitutional Protection of Human Rights”,
Journal of Politics and Law, Vol 1, No 3: 73-78.
Kachhwaha, Kavita (2011): “Khap Adjudication in India: Honouring the Culture with Crimes”,
International Journal of Criminal Justice Sciences, Vol 6, Iss 1-2: 297-308.
Kirti, Anand, Prateek Kumar and Rachana Yadav (2011): “The Face of Honour Based Crimes: Global Concerns and Solutions”,
International Journal of Criminal Justice Sciences, Vol 6, Iss 1-2: 343-57.
Madsen, Stig Toft (1991): “Clan, Kinship and Panchayat Justice among the Jats of Western Uttar Pradesh”,
Anthropos, Bd 86, H 4./6: 351-65.
Mhatre, Ujjwala (2010): “The Question of Democracy and Khap Panchayats”,
Social Modernity: Asian Journal of Social Science, Vol 1, Iss 1-2: 68-78.
Mody, Perveez (2002): “Love and the Law: LoveMarriage in Delhi”,
Modern Asian Studies,
Vol 36, No 1: 223-56.
Nussbaum, Martha (2010): “A Right to Marry”,
California Law Review, Vol 98, Iss 3, 667-96, accessed from: htp://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/californialawreview/vol98/iss3/1 on 12
April 2013 at 12:36 am
Palombella, Gianluigi (2006):
From Human Rights to Fundamental Rights: Consequences of a Conceptual Distinction, Report No34 (
http://ssrn.com/abstract=963754): EUI Working Papers.
Turner, Terence (1997): “Human Rights, Human Difference: Anthropology’s Contribution to an Emancipatory Cultural Politics
”, Journal of Anthropological Research, Vol 53, No 3: 273-91.
Vishwanath, Jyothi and Srinivas Palakonda (2011): “Patriarchal Ideology of Honour and Honour Crimes in India”,
International Journal of Criminal Justice Sciences, Vol 6, Iss 1-2: 386-95.
Welchman, Lynn and Sara Hossain (2005): “Introduction: ‘Honour’, Rights and Wrongs” in by Lynn Welchman and Sara Hossain,
‘Honour’: Crimes, Paradigms and Violence against Women (London: Zed Books), 1-21.
Yadav, Bhupendra (2009): “Khap Panchayats: Stealing Freedom?”,
Economic & Political Weekly, Vol XLIV, No 52: 16-19, 26 December.
Zechenter, Elizabeth (1997): “In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual”,
Journal of Anthropological Research, Vol 53, No 3: 319-47.